Brains:
Philosophical Zombies, Thought Experiments and Consciousness
The
thought experiment of the philosophical zombie has found itself an audience of
supporters and detractors. Modern
adaptations of this concept have extended further to include entire worlds
populated by the philosophically undead.
This philosophical zombie asks us to thing about the nature of
consciousness, all the while pondering whether zombies can exist. Additionally, this experiment demonstrates the
limitations of thought experiments and the limitations of our own
consciousness. In this essay, the most
common explanation of the philosophical zombie will be expressed. The various sides of the thought experiment
will be explained as well. The
conclusion will demonstrate how this particular experiment fails.
The
thought experiment of the philosophical zombie was written about extensively by
David Chalmers in his 1996 book The
Conscious Mind. This work built on
the prior ideas of philosophers like Saul Kripke. The philosophical zombie is a creature, not a
person, who is, molecule for molecule identical to an ordinary living,
breathing human being, except for one important difference; the zombie has no
consciousness. It looks and feels just
like any sentient being on the planet but does not feel or think. This zombie twin has physical function and
physiological organization the same as people.
Additionally, behavior is replicated by neurologic function. For example, should the zombie be prodded
with a red hot fireplace stoker then the zombie would react in the same painful
manner as any ‘normal’ human. Since we
can conceive of such a creature, as the argument goes, they are possible, at
least metaphysically. Had the
circumstances of the natural world been different, zombies could have very well
existed or exist (Kobes, 2007). Ultimately,
the experiment is an argument against the idea that everything in our world has
a physical basis, including consciousness.
The
debate today is rather vigorous. Some
argue that any zombie like that in this thought experiment could not be exactly
like us. Aspects of our perception, a
part of our consciousness, would not be available to the zombie. And, if our consciousness is a causal
relationship between sensory inputs and behavioral outputs, there is no way for
the zombie to be, molecule for molecule, like a person (Pratt, 2013). Essentially, if it walks like a human and it
quacks like a human then it must be a human.
Others argue that a zombie could evaluate their visual perceptions in
terms of environmental contrast and behaving in that environment. The counter argument is that since the zombie
lacks a ‘normal’ consciousness, experiences and perceptions are not a factor. Another group of philosophers state that,
once a zombie comes into being and begins interacting with its environment that
those experiences start to form a type of consciousness (Pratt, 2013). A fourth group argues that any being, or
creature, with analytical mechanisms, would experience consciousness. If this philosophical zombie is biologically
identical to sentient humans, then they would experience some sort of consciousness
(Loosemore, 2009). As zombies search for
brains, they must interact with their environment and analyze and experience
their surroundings. Some do not argue
about the veracity of the philosophical zombie, rather they state that the
argument itself is circular and, therefore, not valid. The idea that something physically identical
to a human being but lacking subjective experience would assume that subjective
experiences do not produce consciousness, which is what the experiment is
trying to prove (Brown).
All
of these stances, arguments and counter arguments suppose that we know
something about consciousness. However,
this supposition leads to a very difficult problem, what Chalmers calls the
‘hard problem.’ To date, no scholar,
philosopher or academic has proved, convincingly, a casual explanation of how
and why we are conscious. There has been
no conclusive evidence showing that we are not, in fact, zombies (Harnad). To many, consciousness has multiple meanings. Consciousness can mean that a being is
‘awake,’ alert and aware of one’s surroundings.
Taken a step further, it can also mean that the ability to have
intentions, purposeful thoughts and behaviors.
To conceive of a thing is also to conceive of what that thing
lacks. Therein lies the problem. How can we conceive of a thing that cannot,
itself conceive of that thing that we cannot even define (Loosemore, 2009)?
It
is very easy for any individual to conceive of zombies. The
Walking Dead, Sean of the Dead, Night of the Living Dead and Zombieland are but a few examples of
zombies in popular media. As such,
zombies are definitely possible in one’s imagination. This thought experiment is based on the
assumption that what we can conceive must be possible. This shows a limitation of thought
experiments themselves. All thought
experiments, from the Chinese Room to a tree falling in the forest, rely on
conceiving a certain set of properties. And,
while truth might be stranger than fiction, the fictions that can be conceived
by humans can be complex and varied.
Ultimately, any conceived parameters and properties are just that:
fictions created in one’s imagination.
A
better thought experiment could easily be found. One would be to simply imagine two identical
human beings living on two different planets.
One could be called Bob(Earth) and Bob(Mars) and their consciousness
could be debated. However, there already
exist two identical individuals on this planet: identical twins. We can call this the Twins Experiment. Their experiences can be created and
conceived. Then, their consciousness can
be debated and examined. Various
philosophers and scholars can publish volumes on the subject. Perhaps, this experiment may yield some
answers; perhaps, it may arrive at a definition of what constitutes
consciousness.
However,
for the sake of the thought experiment, this author will ponder whether such a
creature could exist and what it might mean for our consciousness. Zombies lack agency, the ability to perform
actions in the world. Performing
behaviors requires some thought, some ability to have a meaningful actions,
even if it is only for brains.
Therefore, any actions made by such a zombie must be governed by
extraneous electrical impulses that can contract muscles or by our autonomous
and parasympathetic nervous systems.
However, it seems implausible that, without a consciousness, we would
only want to consume human flesh. If
that were the case, that zombies function on mere impulse, but can we call the
unfortunate soul on hospital life support a zombie? After all, they could react to certain stimuli. It would hardly seem appropriate to call them
zombies. Perhaps this is because we
conceive of zombies like those in 28 Days
Later. Supposing that zombies are
logically possible requires at least two beliefs. First, that something can be true if it can
be conceived. Simply put, zombies are
not possible with the current natural order of things. Put another way, the existence of zombies
have not empirical truth. The reality of
a philosophical zombie requires belief in conceptual truth, that what can be
imagined has the ability to be real.
Second, that consciousness must be something that transcends words which
would draw into question the appropriateness and veracity of any thought
experiment dealing with consciousness.
After all, a thought experiment ceases to be a thought experiment if
they are so implausible as to elicit more discussion about the validity of the
experiment than engagement with the experiment itself.
References
Brown,
R. (2010). Deprioritizing the a priori arguments against physicalism. Journal of Consciousness Studies,
17(3-4), 47-69.
Harnad,
S. (1995). Why and how we are not zombies.
Journal of Consciousness Studies, 1(2), 164-167.
Kobes,
B.W. (2007). Functionalist Theories of Consciousness. In T. Bayne, A. Cleeremans & P. Wilken
(Eds.), Oxford Companion to Consciousness.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Loosemore,
R.P.W. (2009). Consciousness in human and machine: A theory and some falsifable
predictions. In B. Goertzel, P. Hitzler & M. Hutter (Eds.), Proceedings of the Second Conference on
Artificial General Intelligence (Arlington, March 2009). Paris: Atlantis
Press.
Pratt,
M. (2013). Redefining the class of qualitative states – A reply to Shoemaker. Res Cogitans, 4(1), 52-62.
No comments:
Post a Comment